A trifling debt makes a man your debtor; a large one makes him an enemy.
-Seneca the Younger
Yesterday, the, dare I say, always-worth-reading Paul Krugman wrote on the on the hazards of deliberating in “Nobody Understands Debt”: “Why is deleveraging a problem? Because my spending is your income, and your spending is my income, so if everyone slashes spending at the same time, incomes go down around the world.” Mr. Krugman provides the orthodox Keynesian diagnosis of deleveraging in terms of aggregate demand and it doing so reveals the flaws of the aggregate-demand approach: It ignores the ecological qualities of the markets.
To really understand whether people’s spending reflects the wealth of the nation, we have to understand the context in which people are trucking, bartering and exchanging. The economy is a coordination problem where profits are to be had by bringing people’s future plans into greater coordination with each other. Wealth, in turn, is fit order that correctly anticipates people’s future appetites and is thereby coordinated with them.
Any process of deleveraging therefore needs to be understood in a coordination perspective. Such a process, however painful, can be necessary if there is widespread mal-coordination within the economy. In a 2010 study, “Debt and Deleveraging: The global credit bubble and its economic consequences,” the authors, Roxburg et al., addressed such mistaken activity when it wrote about how the level of debt in most mature countries aggressively expanded after 2000 due to “unusually low interest rates and risk spreads…” (Roxburgh et al. 2010: 10). Later in the study, Roxburgh et al. specifically point to the leverage of households as being an economic problem post-2008:
Taking a more granular view of leverage within sectors of the economy, we find that households increased their borrowing substantially, particularly through home mortgages. Rising housing prices meant that the ratio of household debt to assets appeared stable in the years prior to the crisis. But household debt compared with disposable income increased significantly, which should have raised a red flag long before the crisis. (Ibid)
Leverage just isn’t a data point; rather, it’s the manifestation of economic life. Whether it’s a manifestation that adequately corresponds with the demands of life is another matter. The markets can and do lead to situations where the patterns of specialization and trade that have hitherto evolved are, for one reason for another, unsuited to the demands of life. Roxburgh et al. write of a credit bubble that led to households holding an unsustainable level of debt, compared to their income, once economic reality reasserted itself.
Mr. Krugman is correct in asserting that debt per se is nothing, “it does not directly make the economy poorer (and paying it off doesn’t make us richer)” What makes us poorer or richer is how our economic life, the patterns of specialization and The moment that people realize the departure of the two is, like most sudden revelations, a moment of crisis—the crash of the housing market was certainly devastating for those who had based their economic life on it.
Once such bubbles have burst, spending needs to go down so that people can figure out the most profitable ways of doing business with one another. Deleveraging can be a necessary part of that natural process. The way forward isn’t to deny that people borrowed too much, it’s to accept that people have to adapt themselves to the demands of economic life and deleveraging, as described by Roxburgh et al., can be a necessary part of that process. Economic life, after all, is a coordination problem. Even if that coordination problem may be somewhat of a mass hallucination, it is still a mass hallucination that people have to adapt to if they desire to flourishing.
Insofar as deleveraging reflects the aftermath of the extinction of unprofitable patterns of specialization and trade, it reflects an event that enhances the wealth of the nation by bringing people’s economic decisions into better coordination with one another. It is bad when it doesn’t it doesn’t enhance that coordination, which can be the case when there are monetary disturbances—but that’s a topic for another day. The connections created between people through business are complex and ecological, not simple and hydraulic.
Mr. Krugman’s repetition of the tired line that “We owe debt to ourselves” encapsulates the latter perspective. People don’t owe money to themselves; rather, different people in their own distinct stations of life owe money to different people. There’s a politically pertinent reason for not wanting to look at loans in such simplistic terms: The adage that he who holds the purse holds the power is all too true.
The fall of Prime Minister Silvio Berlusconi’s government in Italy following pressure from the bond markets on his government’s finances in 2011 and the rise of Mario Monti’s government of unelected technocrats, just a week after Monti had been appointed a senator for life by President Giorgio Napolitano, should be a lesson in the power of the bond markets as a faction. A modern government cannot operate without access to well-functioning bond markets, which means that bond-holders are a potential faction that can override an otherwise democratic government’s wishes. As long as people have different appetites and different ways of life, then the slogan “We owe it to ourselves” is a delusion. There is no ‘us.’ There’s only a heterogenous population of different people all with their own ends in life, and only a fool bets that people will be publicly spirited when crisis is around the corner.
Edge's Scientific Ideas Ready for Retirement
Edge recently published a roundtable of contributing authors arguing for what scientific idea they think should be abandoned in 2014 in “2014: What Scientific Idea is Ready for Retirement?” Definitely worth at least skimming. Reactions to a few are below:
Nassim Nicholas Taleb argues that we need to retire the concept of standard deviation, which is both inferior to mean deviation and has been masquerading as that more sound concept ever since Karl Pearson introduced it in 1893:
Deirdre McCloskey and Stephen T. Ziliak’s The Cult of Statistical Significance is another compelling criticism of the problem of the mechanistic application of statistics to problems of society. When statistics are going to be used, the practitioner cannot simply apply cookbook formulas if he is going to get the soundest conclusions; instead, he must understand the way in which statistics manipulates data in order to make statements about wider phenomena. The difference between standard and mean deviation is an example of where practitioners need to get a best grasp of the tools they use. The advent of every practitioner being able to have a powerful computer has also alleviated the need for statisticians to rely on simpler means of calculation - one possible reason why the frequentist view of statistics won out against the Bayesian - and has made it possible for practitioners to integrate more demanding calculations within their statistics.
Peter Richerson, a biologist who is emeritus at the University of California, Davis, argues that the concept of human needs to be abandoned this year for an understanding based on variance:
The problem with Richerson’s argument here is that, in course of making an argument against the notion of human nature, he makes claims which strongly resemble claims about human nature. The assertion that a third of people are saints, a tenth of devils in disguise, and the rest somewhere in between looks very much like an answer to the essentialist question of whether people are either good or evil. The assumption that such a question must be answered on a binary scale of either yes or no is simply a caricature of the study of human nature.
At its best, the study of human nature is the study of certain propensities within humanity which are universal across human societies, like the Westermarck effect and a concern for purity. Even though Richerson’s criticisms of a naïve view of human nature which conceives of human nature as “causally prior to nurture both in evolutionary and developmental time,” its insights simply do not apply to more nuanced approach, like that within Edward O. Wilson’s book On Human Nature.
Adam Waytz argues against the idea that humans are by nature social animals:
Again, a problem that I have with Wytz’s argument is that he isn’t very generous to what people are talking about when they speak of humans as social animals. He says that the concept “has lent credibility to numerous significant ideas: that humans need other humans to survive, that humans tend to be perpetually ready for social interaction, and that studying specifically the social features of human functioning is profoundly important.” It seems that Wytz equivocates the claim that human beings have a propensity towards forming social relationships with the claim that human beings are altruistic, ever extroverted saints. Anybody who has read Darwin’s Descent of Man knows that that is not true, and that social propensities are often parochial propensities. Nevertheless, they are still there, and human beings have the biological capability to be social in a way otherwise unseen in the animal kingdom.
Posted by Harrison Searles on 01/15/2014 at 06:49 PM in Commentary, Conjecture and Refutation, Nassim Nicholas Taleb, Neither Angel nor Devil | Permalink | Comments (0)
Reblog (0) | | |