From Thomas C. Schelling’s chapter "The Retarted Science of International Strategy" in The Strategy of Conflict:
As a matter of fact, many of the critical elements that go into a model of rational behavior can be identified with particular types of rationality and irrationality. The value system, the communication system, the information system, the collective decision process, the parameter representing the probability of error or loss of control, can be viewed as an effort to formalize the study of ‘irrationality.’ Hitler, the French Parliament, the commander of a bomber, the radar operators at Pearl Harbor, Khrushchev, and the American electorate may all suffer from some kinds of ‘irrationality,’ but by no means the same kind (Schelling 1980, 16-17).
Earlier in the same article, Schelling speaks "an understanding of 'correct' play" which can "give us a bench mark for the study of action behavior" (Ibid, 3). Schelling’s wisdom is in identifying the standard of rationality, not as a set of transcendent normative criteria, being embedded within the particular circumstances facing each agent. Such an approach is worth following since it pays attention to the particular situations in which behavior occurs, and doesn't fall into the conceit as to think that what it means to be rational can be easily elucidated in a journal article.
There is something to rational behavior which separates it from other behaviors. There are dimensions to decision making, like choosing what beliefs to to act upon or what motives to follow, which give reason for there to be a standard for fitting conduct like rationality. When talking about rationality, generally what we want to do is to discover a normative criteria and to figure out how actual behavior deviates from that criteria. Hitler, for instance, would certainly not have been rational if he decided to invade Russia if made that suggestion on the belief of the Wermacht's racial superiority, or if he had done so out of anger rather than a strategic calculus of whether the war was winnable.
Earlier in the same article, Schelling speaks "an understanding of 'correct' play" which can "give us a bench mark for the study of action behavior" (Ibid, 3). Schelling’s wisdom is in identifying the standard of rationality, not as a set of transcendent normative criteria, being embedded within the particular circumstances facing each agent. Such an approach is worth following since it pays attention to the particular situations in which behavior occurs, and doesn't fall into the conceit as to think that what it means to be rational can be easily elucidated in a journal article.
Etymology matters. In Cratylus, Plato’s argues that words are mortal gropings towards immortal meanings. In Essays on the First Formation of Language, Adam Smith’s arguesthat words are focal points for human conversation about the world, remembering the meanings of words is important for our comprehension of the ideas that are behind them. The word ‘rationality’ derives from the Latin word ‘ratio’ which, according to the ever reliable Wikitionary, is “1. A number representing a comparison between two things.” It cannot be described simply as ordinal preferences and transitivity, or as goal-orientated behavior; instead, rationality is a matter of focal standards which provided a bench mark for judging whether the behavior in question reached a standand which could be expected from it. When scholarship cannot make sense of ordinary language, it’s a sign that something has gone drastically wrong. Such is the case with rationality.
Collapsing rationality into little, or nothing, more than a description of all human action fails to live up to that conception that behavior can be judged according to standards and thereby judged rational or irrational. There are actually interesting questions intertwined with the word ‘rationality.’ In ordinary language, people use the word in ways that simply collapsing it to encompass all human behavior disappoints. There are such things that are used as focal standards for judging the rationality of human action. What those focal standards are is an interesting question which shines light upon the human condition, and which consequently shouldn't be defined out of existence.
Moreover, what those focal standards are all too often cannot be understood outside of a deep understanding of the context in which they occur. Speaking of the irrationality of Hitler or the French Parliament requires an understanding of the context they made their decisions within so that one can talk about the standards which Hitler or the French Parliament are to be judged by.
In the end, rationality is a matter of matching behavior with its focal standard, and what that focal standard is will depend on the situation each agent faces. There can be many ways in which different types of action and different types of plans can live up to rationality because they are judged by different focal standards. That something is rational within one circumstance and irrational is another is neither a contradiction, but rather a consequence of the fact that what it means to be rational depends on the factors at play within each circumstance.
Liberty and the Anglosphere: Reflections on Hannan's _Inventing Liberty_
The nations, not so blest as thee,
Must, in their turns, to tyrants fall;
While thou shalt flourish great and free,
The dread and envy of them all.
In his recent book, Inventing Liberty: How the English-Speaking Peoples Made the Modern World, MEP Daniel Hannan discusses how the ideas of a liberal society emerged within the British isles over a course of hundreds of years, and how their proliferation across the world happened within a distinctly English-speaking context. Hannan argues that it has been the ascendency of the Anglosphere in the past three hundred years, including nations like the United States, Canada, and Australia, which has made possible the similar ascendency of liberal values over that same time period. Hannan argues that it was the culture of common law, of Magna Carta, and of representative government, not intellectual arguments, which made the free and open society possible. As intellectuals discussed (and eventually en masse rejected) the values which cultivated such a society, they were transported to and flowered in British colonies the world over, even amongst the prisoners shipped to Australia.
The main question, at least for me, which Inventing Liberty brings up is the question of how culture has made liberalism possible. A constant problem facing any order at the level of society at large is: How do people participate within them? As every angsty teenager has recognized, sometimes society can be an impersonal machine in which people can be but cogs, used as means rather than as ends in and of themselves. As Shakespeare wrote: All the world's a stage/ And all the men and women merely players. What guides those players, and forms their collective patterns of behavior into what we know as as society are the institutions and norms of the societies which people find themselves surrounded by. The way that people participate in the social orders they live in is thus often merely a product of the culture they are surrounded by.
Of course, we all know (and for the most part appreciate) that institutions matter. But there is something quite different between the argument which Hannan is making, and the arguments which many institution-matter theorists make is that Hannan argues, implicitly though, that we cannot simply replicate the institutions of the Anglosphere to non-Anglosphere countries. The necessary jump between Hannan’s main point in Inventing Liberty and an institutions-matter theorist like James Buchanan’s throughout his corpus is that Hannan’s vision is very much historically fatalistic whereas Buchahan looks at the problem from the point of view of social contract theory. For Buchahan, the question what can be done is a very real one, though in Hannan, what can be done is largely just a matter of preserving what is already there. In Hannan's history, institutions are determined by culture, and if a nation does not have the culture to support good institutions, then it is by and large doomed to go without them.
The British character of liberalism and of the commercial society it animates is corroborated by common language. When people are speaking about the core tenet of a liberal market, competition, people, especially in Continental Europe, often speak of “Anglo-Saxon capitalism.” The view that it is that British variety which encourages “dog-eat-dog” competition whereas their more “cooperative” approach cultivated more moral outcomes. The use of such language is so wide that it has gotten its own page of Wikipedia: “The Anglo-Saxon Model.” The culturally English-speaking nature of the modern commercial society is thereby displayed by its identification with a certain cultural group, that of Great Britiain.
The question which I am naturally lead to is then: Why Britain? Why did the English-speaking population become the cradle of liberal ideas rather than, say the populations of Holland or Italy? The Dutch certainly went a long way towards the development of liberal ideas, and during the Dutch Golden Age, Amsterdam was a shining light in the world. There, the first modern stock market was established there by the Dutch East India Company in 1602. Levels of religious toleration were high compared to the rest of Europe, especially towards the Jews (though the Catholics suffered due to perceived political loyalties to the Habsburg empire that the Dutch Republic had succeeded from). Daniel Hannan even celebrates Dutch society in “I realised why I like the Dutch so much,” and claims that what he loves about Dutch society is found in the bourgeois values that the Dutch and British both share: “Only recently, though, was I able to put my finger on what I liked so much. It’s this: for centuries, the Dutch made the honest pursuit of self-betterment a supreme virtue.” The bourgeois virtues which Deirdre McCloskey celebrates in her aptly named book, The Bourgeois Virtues, were quickly coming to fruition within Amsterdam, and the Dutch Republic could therefore have seemed to be a viable candidate to be the cradle of liberalism for the Western world.
That was not to be, though. One of the main reasons was that the Dutch Republic did not have Great Britain’s fortunate geography. Unlike Great Britain, which is an island separated from the Continent, the Netherlands is a low-lying plain, much of it reclaimed from the sea, close to the center of Europe. As such, the influenced of the bourgeois virtues in the Netherlands was vulnerable of being snuffed out by conquest, and that is one of the events which happened following the Dutch Golden Age. Whereas the British were able to survive and compete against the Continental powers by outdoing them on the seas, the Dutch Republic never had such an option, and like the Polish-Lithuanian Commonwealth was unable to assert its independence forever against the encroachments of illberal states very adept at waging war. Unlike those two, Great Britain was in the fateful position of being separated by the sea from the many wars which were waged on the Continent in the early modern period, and was thereby separated from the need of winning those wars, at the cost of its liberal values, in order to ensure its survival.
In the end, liberalism wasn’t discovered by the great powers of human reason; rather, it was cultivated in culture until finally being recognized by the mind. It is not a necessary outcome of progress. Rather, it is a historical accident. The ascendency of liberalism is thus not a matter, as it often is depicted to be, of the triumph of human reason over bigotry and superstition. Instead, the ascendency of liberalism is a matter of a historically contingent sequence of unique events in unique places; of infectous habits rather than explicit ideas. The lesson to be appreciated from Daniel Hannan’s Inventing Liberty is that the free and open society is a consequence not of human ideas, but of human history.
Posted by Harrison Searles on 01/09/2014 at 11:00 AM in Commentary, Culture, Daniel Hannan, Liberalism, Political Philosophy, Rationality, Rules and Order, The Commercial Society, The Free and Open Society | Permalink | Comments (0)
Reblog (0) | | |