I wrote before about the paradigmatic differences between the approaches taken between the Austrians and New Classicals in how they approach economics. The differences go as deep as how the two paradigms even think about economics as a science.
Certainly there is a heterogeneity to both paradigms to how they approach the scientific status of economics, Mises taking a harder line than Hayek for instance. Nevertheless, there are stark differences between the two. Those differences are revealed in the banquet speeches Hayek and Lucas each gave when receiving their Nobel Memorial Prizes in 1974 and 1995 respectively.
In his banquet speech, Hayek was skeptical of whether the Prize, only five years old at the time, was a good thing. He argued that the institution of a Nobel Memorial Prize for economics would give economics too much prestige:
(T)he Nobel Prize confers on an individual an authority which in economics no man ought to possess.
This does not matter in the natural sciences. Here the influence exercised by an individual is chiefly an influence on his fellow experts; and they will soon cut him down to size if he exceeds his competence.
But the influence of the economist that mainly matters is an influence over laymen: politicians, journalists, civil servants and the public generally.
There is no reason why a man who has made a distinctive contribution to economic science should be omnicompetent on all problems of society - as the press tends to treat him till in the end he may himself be persuaded to believe.
Economists certainly have valuable things to contribute to the rest of society. Basic Econ 101, if fully understood, would greatly augment the general welfare. As Peter Boettke keeps saying, simple economics is not simple-minded economics.
However, as economics moves beyond Econ 101, the ground that economists stand on does not adequately reflect their ambitions, and so one can get contradictory answers from Nobel-Memorial Prize Winners on basic questions as whether there is a trade off between inflation and unemployment. The Swedish Riksbank surrounding practitioners of such a discipline with the mystique of a hard science, as a Nobel is bound to do, can lead to the creation of a dangerous class of technocrats whose advice, however flawed, is accepted by virtue of a Nobel’s prestige.
The hope that a Nobel could serve as a focal point for the recognition of what it means to be a good economist was flawed because there were no feedback mechanisms for updating people’s esteem of different economists. In the physical sciences, those that babbled nonsense would quickly be revealed for the charlatans they are by the data, but economics does not have recourse to such mechanisms. It’s not that, as many continue to argue, that economics doesn’t care about data, it’s that even pinning down the concept of economic data is surprisingly difficult. Hayek commented on this predicament in his Prize lecture:
Unlike the position that exists in the physical sciences, in economics and other disciplines that deal with essentially complex phenomena, the aspects of the events to be accounted for about which we can get quantitative data are necessarily limited and may not include the important ones. While in the physical sciences it is generally assumed, probably with good reason, that any important factor which determines the observed events will itself be directly observable and measurable, in the study of such complex phenomena as the market, which depend on the actions of many individuals, all the circumstances which will determine the outcome of a process, for reasons which I shall explain later, will hardly ever be fully known or measurable. And while in the physical sciences the investigator will be able to measure what, on the basis of a prima facie theory, he thinks important, in the social sciences often that is treated as important which happens to be accessible to measurement. This is sometimes carried to the point where it is demanded that our theories must be formulated in such terms that they refer only to measurable magnitudes.
Hayek’s skepticism about whether economics has a scientific character for which the Nobel Memorial could serve as a focal point is contrasted with Robert Lucas’ optimism. In Lucas’ banquet speech, he argued that the Nobel Memorial Prize was a valuable institution which served as a focal point for scientific exploration:
This prize was established in the 1960s, as a memorial, through the generosity of the Bank of Sweden. Generosity and, I would say, wisdom, as the establishment of a Nobel Prize in Economics has had a very beneficial effect on my profession, encouraging us to focus on basic questions and scientific method. It is as if by recognizing Economics as a science, the Bank of Sweden and the Nobel Foundation have helped us to become one, to come close to realizing our scientific potential.
Whereas Hayek is wary of the effects the Nobel Memorial Prize in Economic Sciences would have a positive effect on discourse, Lucas is optimistic. Lucas argued that the Prize heightened economists’ appreciation for basic principles, and the scientific character of their discipline. Prize Winners could serve as focal points for what it means to do good economics, and therefore advances economists’ notion of what it means to be a good economist.
In Lucas’ view, the Nobel Memorial Prize serves well as a feedback mechanisms for the economics community to recognize good economics. Hayek is much more pessimistic, and feared the Prize would have too great an impact on the minds of those outside of economics proper.
The difference between the two, perhaps slight perhaps not, reveals that the two thought about economics differently. Hayek thought about it as a squishy, so to speak, discipline which did not have recourse to the same methods that the physical sciences had for ending disputes among its practitioners. Lucas thought, and continues to think of it, as a harder affair with the potential of such a science.